Page 18 - AECA.org.uk ¦ Koinonia 68
P. 18

Another term  Plato uses to characterize space is διάστημα, interval or
       distance, but again we find  that this means not just measurable distance,  but
       any distance or extension, including moving in an argument, say, from premises
       to a conclusion, or the ‘distance’ implicit in the notion of desire for something.
       The notion  of  multitude or the manifold is implicit in the realm of becoming
       and  διάστημα  is  implicit in  this.  It  is not so  much a  physical concept,  as a
       metaphysical one. The notion of interval applies to time as well, but again does
       so  in  a  multitude  of  ways.  Perhaps  most  important is the  sense  of  time  as
       bound up with cosmic movement, the movement of the heavens: the sequence
       of the seasons, the passage from evening to morning. This cosmic movement is
       more than physical movement, for it has significance, meaning, bound up with
       the  quality  of  time  characteristic  of  the  seasons—spring,  summer,  autumn,
       winter  (vividly  expressed  in  medieval  calendars,  not  least  those  found—
       significantly—in  books  of  hours)—and  of  the  passage  from  evening,  though
       night, to morning and the day. The creation in six days suggests a sequence of
       ages,  prefigured  in  the successive  days of creation, including  the ‘ages of  the
       world’,  variously  conceived.  There  are  also  the  stages  of  human  life,  often
       modeled  on  the ages of  the world:  from  birth to  death,  through the ages  of
       man (variously divided, sometimes four—childhood, youth, maturity, old age—
       sometimes seven—as in Jaques’ infant, student, lover,  soldier, judge,  declining
                                                             5
       into old age, and finally ‘second childishness and mere oblivion’).  Furthermore,
       there is the movement of the soul from its baptismal awakening by repentance,
       through  growth  in  the  image  of  God  by  ascetic  struggle,  and  a  deepening
       transfiguration through grace in which the life of God is manifest in  the soul,
       to deification. All these experiences of movement suggest mutual analogies; it
       is  not,  as  the  modern  mind  is  tempted  to  think,  that  physical  space  and
       duration  are  the  ‘real’  meaning  of  space  and  time,  the  others  being  merely
       metaphorical. Rather all these experiences of movement in space and time are
       experiences of  the modalities of  creaturely being, characterized  by διάστημα.
       Plato’s conviction of the link, or harmony, between the soul and the cosmos is
       manifest in the closing paragraphs of the Timaeus, where he speaks of ‘the most
       sovereign form of soul in us’, which ‘dwells in the summit of our body and lifts
       us from earth towards our celestial affinity, like a  plant whose roots are not in
       earth, but in the heavens’, and recommends that, because ‘the motions akin to
       the  divine part in  us  are the  thoughts  and  revolutions  of  the  universe’,  we

       5  For Jaques’ speech, see Shakespeare, As You Like It, Act II, Scene 7. For some sense of the richness
       of the notion of the ages of man, see J.A. Burrow, The Ages of Man, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986.


                                       16
   13   14   15   16   17   18   19   20   21   22   23